From: Cervantes: Bulletin of the Cervantes Society of America
2.2 (1982): 171-80.
Copyright © 1982, The Cervantes Society of America
CRITIQUE/DIALOG |
|
|
ARTHUR EFRON |
N COMPOSING
my short paper on the bearded waiting women, the lovely lethal female
piratemen, and the rest of the sexual boundary shifts in Part II of the
Quixote,* I had a strategy in mind. My strategy
was to bring before the reader some vivid and disturbing body images of
Cervantes' creation, and, of course, to try to say something of their
significance. Given my strategy, I thought that no one would be able to deny
the importance of the body, that in fact there would be some who would want
to do some serious thinking about it, even if some would want to offer a
different interpretation. Did I succeed? There are points at which Cesáreo
Bandera seems to accept my strategy. The most notable is his realization
that what I am talking about is not the concept of the body, but the
real thing, my body for me, his body for him, her body for her, etc.
And when Dr. Bandera discovers that according to my reading of Cervantes,
we can say that Like a leech or a parasite, authority feeds on the
body . . . , I am disposed to grant his grasp of what
I basically mean. Yet aside from these and a few other snippets, my strategy
seems to have failed with Bandera, as it well might with other readers. I
say it has failed because much before the end of Bandera's disputation, the
body has lost its prominence, even though that is a prominence that not I
but
* This current piece is a response to
Cesáreo Bandera, Healthy Bodies in
Not-So-Healthy Minds, Cervantes 2.2
(1982): 165-70, which was a reaction to Arthur Efron's original paper,
Bearded Waiting Women, Lovely Lethal Female Piratemen:
Sexual Boundary Shifts in Don Quixote, Part II Cervantes
2.2 (1982): 155-164. -F.J.
|
||
172 | ARTHUR EFRON | Cervantes |
|
Cervantes gave it. Bandera disposes of the problem expertly, finding in his
fourth paragraph that the solution becomes obvious, and that
there is no basis whatsoever to the opposition of natural body
and unnatural society. There is not even any relevance to what
I am talking about. Bandera suggests there is a simple explanation to the
images of the body that I have focused upon in my paper, namely that they
all might be seen as a reflection of the collapse or mismanagement
of social authority, since we see so many outlaws, and we also see so many
people in authority, like the Duke and the Duchess, stepping below the dignity
of their functions in a manner which is explicitly described as
reprehensible. This provides an obvious, reasonable
explanation.
The trouble with this solution is first of
all that it relieves the discomfort before it is felt; the reader is being
advised to forget the prominence of the vivid body images and look to the
obvious, reasonable explanation, which is a rather
traditional one. Thus Melisendra's sliced off nose, the two dead Spanish
sailors, the many bandits hanging from trees, the lethal lady Claudia
Gerónima, the bearded waiting women, and Sancho's repeatedly exposed,
whipped (but not really) buttocks, require no lingering over, no receptivity,
no disturbance, and no discussion. Bandera does not discuss them. They were
the problem I wanted to have readers confront.
Bandera has reasons for this refusal, but even
if these were good reasons they could never be good enough. Sancho's buttocks
are there, in Cervantes' masterpiece. There can be no excuse for dodging
them. The critical record shows that by and large, the buttocks of Sancho
as well as all the other disturbing body images I have brought to attention,
and the whole topic of the human body, have been evaded. Instead we have
been given reasonable and sometimes purportedly obvious
explanations for the gross, the grotesque, the irrational.
Bandera is too good a reader to really place
much stock in his own counter-explanations, when these bump directly against
the Quixote. Would the contribution of civilization toward increased
longevity really be appropriate as a counter-argument? Bandera himself is
content merely to insinuate that it must mean something, without trying to
bring it to bear as an argument; surely it would be ridiculous to explain
the whipping and Sancho's being loved by his master along those lines, and
in any case, Bandera knows, from my
|
||
2 (1982) | Some Central Issues in Quixote Criticism | 173 |
|
article, The Problem of Don Quixote's
Rage,1 that it is not the mere survival
of the body that I am talking about but of the body in adult sexual life.
I doubt also that Bandera has much faith in the way that the Duke and Duchess
are explicitly described as reprehensible. All such description
is the moral commentary either of Cide Hamete Benengeli, a narrator of no
great perspicacity let alone reliability in these matters, or of some other
character whose testimony would have to be evaluated critically and not accepted
as obvious.2 My objection to the
obvious is directed toward better contact with Cervantes' novel.
Can we, after the Galley Slave scene in I, 22, safely assume that it is the
mismanagement of social authority that is at stake, or is it
social authority itself, operating quite astutely, that sends the prisoners
to their punishment for such dubious reasons as Don Quixote brings out in
his questioning?3 I object to the
obvious also from a basis in political argument: the recourse
to the obvious explanation that it is only the mismanagement
of social authority and not its essence, can be taken automatically,
without limit. Usually it is, by someone or other who has something to defend.
In Don Quixote and the Dulcineated World, (pp. 178-79) I gave the
example of the New Laws of the Indies, developed because of the reformer,
Bartolomé de las Casas. In Bandera's fashion, some maintain that these
Laws, mandating justice to the Indians under Spanish Colonial rule, were
the authority, while the actual destruction of most of the Indian
populace was merely the mismanagement of authority. I confess
an ultimate lack of faith in the distinction, which is not to deny that on
occasion it can be made to hold.
Although Bandera declines to linger over Sancho's
buttocks, or any of the other episodes I discussed, he does bring up one
episode from Don Quixote itself. That is the story of the poet
Grisóstomo (Chrysostom) in Part One. If we read again
Grisóstomo's desperate song just before he goes to hell, that
is, before he commits suicide,
1 The
Problem of Don Quixote's Rage, Denver Quarterly 16 (Fall 1981),
29-46.
2 See on this
my Don Quixote and the Dulcineated World (Austin: 1971), pp. 148-49.
3 See
Dulcineated World, pp. 59-62, for a reading of the scene and a treatment
of the alternative critical approaches to it.
|
||
174 | ARTHUR EFRON | Cervantes |
|
we will see that Cervantes is actually writing about people who only imagine
that there is a threat out there in society; these people want
only to convince the world and themselves that the threat is out
there, whereas Cervantes is showing that it is inherent in their own
minds. I willingly grant that Grisóstomo's song is full of imagined
persecution; the cruelties he ascribes to the beautiful Marcela
plainly are not hers but his own projections. The episode, however, does
not give the clear support to Bandera that he needs for his reliance on it
in his dispute with me. Suppose that the episode shows not what the human
imagination alone can build up by way of imagined persecution, but that it
shows this only within the condition of someone already removed from all
contact with the other sex. Lest this sound like too modern a way into Cervantes,
let me quote the character Ambrosio, who tells us of the conditions in which
Grisóstomo wrote his desperate song: . . . I must
tell you that when the unfortunate man wrote this song he had voluntarily
banished himself from Marcela to see if absence would have its customary
effect upon him. And as there is nothing that does not vex the absent
lover . . . , he promptly imagined all sorts of
horrible things about her.4 Grisóstomo
thus does not fit the hypothetical case, suggested by Bandera, of someone
who stays home and lives in moderation, tries to avoid any idealistic dangers
of adventures in literature and society, and takes good care of his bodily
rhythms, particularly as these involve longing for contact with, or
at least an impulse to be near, the loved one. If he did go near her, no
doubt he would be mortified again to discover that she is no lover of his
as far as she is concerned. But that is a more complicated matter than a
man merely dealing with the forces of his own mind, because even as she rejects
him, Marcela shows that she is a real woman and not one of his projections.
His body would certainly feel the rejection at some level, however much he
may try to deny the feeling by idealizing the woman.
Grisóstomo has placed himself in a state
of sexual denial; he is repressing himself, as Bandera would surely point
out. But whoever finds it worthwhile to take up the topic of sexual repression
when it is self-initiated (here I will set aside the issue of where
Grisóstomo got his idea of denial), is presupposing that there is
such a thing as sexual repression, and that it is worth taking seriously
in Don Quixote.
4 Cervantes, The
Adventures of Don Quixote (Harmondsworth: 1950), p. 107.
|
||
2 (1982) | Some Central Issues in Quixote Criticism | 175 |
|
Bandera, however, writes the following: If you are A. Efron,
. . . you can write in your head a novel in which . . .
worst of all, you will show, oh infinite outrage! that [a man] must deny
his healthy sexual urges, by substituting some idealized disgustingly spiritual
and dulcineated maiden, for the real, healthy, plump thing. The tone
and implication here are unmistakable: Bandera is denying that sexual repression
is an important part of the fictional society of the Quixote: it is
only something I have written in my head. He is also denying
that the substitution of an idealized, bodiless or desexualized woman for
a sexual, real woman, is a matter of importance. Indeed the very notion is
ridiculed. To further suggest the unimportance of the issue Bandera introduces
the absurd consideration of being always totally healthy. Bandera
also writes that it is obvious that social power and bodily power
are the same thing . . . . This formulation, too,
denies that there is a significant transformation of sexuality and of the
way the human body is lived, or might be lived, through a process of
socialization. There has been no transformation if what we have at the end
of the process is the same thing that we had at the beginning.
Extremely important and basic issues for
Quixote criticism are at stake here. I am glad of the present opportunity
to say something about them. Insofar as the issue is one of experiencing
the Quixote, it will come down to this: we have a novel in which a
huge emphasis is placed on the idealness of Dulcinea and of numerous other
female figures, and where there is no corresponding ideal of the fully sexual
woman, unidealized. Aldonza the peasant girl is not the same thing
as Dulcinea, nor is there an effort on the part of the knight or of the other
high-minded males to transform their Dulcineas into Aldonzas. The desired
transformation is all in the other direction, that is, to make real women
as ideal as possible, with a carefully controlled and minimized sexuality,
and to live a man's life as if that ideal were either attainable or already
attained. It is very hard work. To deny all this is to cripple the reader's
mind, because it would extirpate most of the novel that the reader is trying
to read. Yet if we follow Bandera's method, I am convinced that that is what
we would have to do.
Insofar as the basic issue concerns the values
and needs of civilization itself, we are dealing with immense assumptions
that not only need to be made overt; they need to be connected with the evidence
that makes them into working assumptions. Let me give an idea of what I mean
by this. Someone claims that bodily power is the
|
||
176 | ARTHUR EFRON | Cervantes |
|
same thing as social power, only looked at from the other, the social pole.
But is it? When a child masturbates, and is forbidden to do so by his or
her parent, the two powers are quite different. One does oppose the other,
and self-regulated decision is in fact taken over by society's pre-decision.
The masturbation taboo has had great impact, and it is a taboo that is now
weakening in many societies. This weakening will make a real difference in
bodily life; the results will not be just more of the same
thing.
Another example, if one is needed, is the current
revival of birthing patterns that avoid the assaultive practices against
the newborn which have become standard in many hospitals. I would take it
as clear that birth without violence is a body/society interface
that is not the same thing as birth with violence.
In his denials and in his treatment of these
issues Bandera is much indebted to the social thought of René Girard,
whose reading of the Quixote I have criticized in my book (pp. 148,
173, 177-78). Elsewhere I have written that Girard's assumptions require
an inborn dualism in which the mind is inherently disposed to make human
beings aim for gratifications that can only be achieved through acts of violence
against the human body. For Girard, violence is inherently linked with the
sacred as a necessity of cultural
organization.5 This would make any discussion
of the bodily costs of social order almost beside the point.
Girard, however, is not unquestionable. As I noted in my article, my own
assumptions about the body lean heavily on the social thought of Wilhelm
Reich. Reich found significance in the example of the youth house.
Some societies have found it feasible to foster a degree of sexual freedom
among youth that is incompatible with the standard justifications for sexual
repression, such as this by Girard: Sexuality leads to quarrels, jealous
rages, mortal combats. It is a permanent source of disorder even within the
most harmonious societies.6 If that
is so, then a society with a youth-house, such as the Trobriand Islanders
had, should have been unlivable. Trobriand adolescents were sent to live
co-educationally in small houses, about four to a house, without adult
supervision, for several years. But as
5 Arthur
Efron, The Mind-Body Problem in Lawrence, Pepper and Reich.
Journal of Mind and Behavior: An Interdisciplinary Journal, 1 (Autumn,
1980), 262.
6 René
Girard, Violence and the Sacred, trans. P. Gregory. (Baltimore: 1977),
p. 35.
|
||
2 (1982) | Some Central Issues in Quixote Criticism | 177 |
|
Reich argued in The Invasion of Compulsory Sex-Morality, expectations
on our part that this would lead to an especially ferocious society proved
totally false. In fact the opposite was the case.
Bandera attributes assumptions about society
and civilization to me that are not mine. The confusions are not uncommon
ones in Quixote criticism. I am said to believe that the
authority evoked and criticized in the Quixote is whole
and powerful, sure of itself, unquestioning and unquestionable.
Social authority always proves stronger . . . than
the claims of the human body. Bandera does not mean to suggest that Spanish
royal authority was in danger of collapse at the time of the Quixote;
we may suppose, for example, that the banishment of the Moors will remain
in force, even if Madrid is going to be asked to entertain a plea for the
readmission of Anna Ricote. On the other hand, Bandera is right to suggest
that Spanish authority was not totally secure or omnipresent. I did not say
that it was.
Bandera apparently has forgotten large portions
of my book on the Quixote: my supposition that perhaps Basilio cleverly
eluded the pressures of society to give up his beloved Quiteria to the mores
of upper-class marriage, my argument that Sancho never allows society to
take from him completely his sense of his body for him, nor does he allow
it to squelch his critical voice that speaks against all such efforts. Cervantes'
novel itself is a joyous imaginative act of liberation, addressed
to the individual reader, as I put it in the last sentence of my
book.7 I have implied, I would have thought,
that the society of the Quixote is not really sure of itself:
hence, its continual and nervous efforts to insure conformity among all the
inhabitants, and the considerable resistance some of then show in conforming
(Fernando, for example, in Part I).
Similarly, Bandera believes that I would draw
a picture of civilization making a victim of the human body, throughout
history. I would remind him, first of all, that he heard me deliver
a paper entitled A New Homage to Catalonia, in which I praised
the social organizations, including that of the affinity group, invented
by the Spanish anarchists.8 There are some
areas of history, in other words,
7
Dulcineated World, pp. 65-96 (on Sancho), 132-36 (on Basilio), 141
(on Cervantes).
8 Unpublished
paper delivered at the Second Congress of the North American Catalan Society,
Yale University, April, 1980, and at [p. 177]
SUNY-Buffalo, May, 1980. Most of what this paper contains can be found
in the review-article by Michael Scrivener on three recent books about Spanish
anarchism, in Telos, 44 (Winter, 1977-78), 208-13.
|
||
178 | ARTHUR EFRON | Cervantes |
|
where the powers of authoritarian civilization have not been supreme. In
In Search of the Primitive: A Critique of Civilization, Stanley Diamond
draws attention to the existence, until recently, of Igbo society, in which
some four million people were organized socially without benefit of central
authority.9 Apparently Bandera's assumption
is that because I oppose authoritarian organization I therefore oppose
organization itself. The Epilogue to Don Quixote
and the Dulcineated World (p. 141) refers explicitly to a need, conveyed
by Cervantes' novel, to organize life in a radically different way.
I admit that there is much in my position that is problematical, but I must
insist that the possibility of non-authoritarian social organization be
considered. I find that Bandera's way of arguing forecloses this possibility
altogether, preventing it from reaching consciousness. I cannot regard that
as a contribution to the serious consideration of the Quixote and
to the major issues of civilization that are inherent in it.
Bandera also ascribes to me the assumption
that the threats of civilization to the natural sexual body are completely
external, whereas, as he reminds us, there is such a thing as violent fantasy
within the human mind itself. I do not deny the existence of sadomasochistic
fantasy. In The Problem of Don Quixote's Rage, I state, in fact,
that while Quixote sees in the giants (to us, windmills), huge amorphous
dangerous bodies that he believes his God (his culture) would like to have
wiped out, these giants are also rooted invitingly within the
deep fantasy of his own emotional life (p. 37). This in no way invalidates
the conflict between society and the body that I have described. To locate
the fantasies within the self as well as within culture is necessary for
any psychology that would hope to deal with the experience of the
Quixote. As Reich put it, society anchors its repressive
ideas in both body and mind, but as he also argued, interestingly, the sheer
existence of a destructive fantasy is no evidence that it is a central
motivating force. The much-ridiculed healthy
9 In
Search of the Primitive: A Critique of Civilization (New Brunswick: 1974),
pp. 37-38. A larger argument of this book is that civilization certainly
does not represent the values of stability and moderation, as Bandera assumes.
The old village in Spain which is Bandera's home has not become the model
for modern civilization.
|
||
2 (1982) | Some Central Issues in Quixote Criticism | 179 |
|
rhythms of the body, including its sexuality, Reich theorized, could
function to prevent sadomasochistic fantasy from becoming central to the
person. Reich aside, these fantasies can be loaded up with our major energies,
or they can be de-energized to the point of remaining dormant. Civilization
largely works toward the former.
Finally, the boring part. Bandera characterizes
me throughout his paper as unaware of any view but my own, and charges that
my argument is self-confirming because of this. Partly this accusation is
due to my failure, as he sees it, to explain the origin of authoritarian
social organization, or as Reich put it, the origin of the
armoring, in body and emotion, by human beings, against themselves.
But there is no greater duty incumbent upon me to explain that origin than
there is on Bandera. I hope I have said enough to discredit his implied
explanation, in the manner of Girard, that it was sheer necessity combined
with ultimate benefit to life, that did it. There is no reason in any case
why Cervantes cannot raise the question of the costs of civilized living
to those who live it, without offering an explanation of origins. Here again,
in this question of origins, I maintain that Bandera has obscured
what might otherwise have been heard.
There is, however, another reason for Bandera's
accusation that I am being dogmatic: I do not bother to explain
why my way of handling the body imagery in the Quixote is superior
to the traditional ways or to any other ways. To Bandera, I seem merely to
gather evidence to fit preconception, without confronting alternative views.
He complains that he can find no clue in my paper as to why society
cannot accept the body. For anyone interested in what I have to say, however,
Bandera's accusations on this score are seriously misleading. Let us take
first the alleged absence of a single clue about why the human body is rejected.
In the very paragraph from which Bandera lifts the objectionable overall
statement, in the six sentences that immediately precede this offending
statement, I discuss the notion of a jirón, or wonderful
vein, that is supposed to be stored within Dulcinea's body (interestingly,
she does have a body, here): the jirón will produce fortune
and lineage comparable with the highest. The clue, if I may be
obvious, is that society cannot admit that the body is unrelated to class
or lineage or fortune; it is finally a natural entity (despite its potential
for symbolic meanings) that contradicts these notions of social hierarchy.
To admit that would be to admit more than hierarchy can afford. It would
be like admitting that the 600,000 millionaires in the U.S. today are not
really superior to
|
||
180 | ARTHUR EFRON | Cervantes |
|
anyone else. And if they are not superior, how is it that they are entitled
to all that money?
This clue, to be sure, is not an expression
of all that I meant in the tentative conclusion (Bandera forgets
this qualifier). There is no need to take my paper on Bearded Waiting
Women . . . as a complete work in itself. It was an
M.L.A. paper scheduled for 20 minutes, offering an exposition of a view of
the body in the Quixote that has been obscured up to now. As such
it cannot be consulted for treatment of alternative interpretations. However,
my book as well as later articles on the Quixote adhere to a policy
of confronting the alternatives in detail. I spend many pages on this in
Don Quixote and the Dulcineated World, after announcing (p. 21) that
it is my intention to do so. In the course of practicing those fine old civilized
values of moderation and organization, Bandera might have noticed my practice,
instead of making me into his theoretical subject who suffers
from a great personal defect. Cesáreo Bandera's strategy was to try
to deflect discussion to this subject. I am sure he did this
for sincerely held reasons. But such strategy can lead to little more than
an in joke. I continue to think that Cervantes criticism needs
and deserves a much better level of relationship.
|
Fred Jehle jehle@ipfw.edu | Publications of the CSA | HCervantes |
URL: http://www.h-net.org/~cervantes/csa/articf82/effron2.htm |